Read The Cosmic Landscape Online

Authors: Leonard Susskind

Tags: #SCI015000

The Cosmic Landscape (49 page)

BOOK: The Cosmic Landscape
9.6Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Knowing that we live in an open, negatively curved universe would be a strong reason to believe that our pocket universe evolved from some point in history during which it was a bubble in an exponentially expanding space. That seems like a clear prediction, but it may be impossible to confirm. The observable universe is just too big, and so far we have seen only a tiny part of it. We simply don’t see enough to know if it is curved or flat.

What about our universe today? Can expanding bubbles of some other environment form, grow, and take over our pocket universe? What would happen to us if we were swallowed by such a bubble? The answer that String Theory suggests is that we will one day be engulfed in a destructive environment, fatal to all life. Remember that all evidence points to our world having a cosmological constant—a bit of vacuum energy. There is no reason why it cannot produce a bubble with smaller energy. And we know that there are such places on the Landscape, namely, the graveyard of universes: supersymmetric regions where the cosmological constant is exactly zero. Wait long enough, and we will find ourselves in just that kind of vacuum. Unfortunately, as I explained in chapter 7, even life forms as alien as superstring theorists probably cannot survive in a supersymmetric world. A supersymmetric universe might be extremely elegant, but the Laws of Physics in such a world do not allow for ordinary chemistry. It’s not just the graveyard of universes: it spells the death of all chemistry-based life.

If it is certain that we will eventually be swallowed in a hostile supersymmetric environment, how long will it take? Is it something that can happen tomorrow, next year, in a billion years? Like all jittery quantum fluctuations, the answer is that it could happen anytime. Quantum mechanics tells us only how likely it is at any given time. And the answer is that it is incredibly unlikely to happen anytime soon. Indeed, it is unlikely to happen in the next billion, trillion, or quadrillion years. The best rough estimates suggest that our world will last for at least a googolplex years and probably a lot longer!
6

Two Views of History

It is hard to see how the populated Landscape viewpoint can be wrong. It follows from well-tested principles. Nevertheless, there are serious matters of concern. Perhaps the most uncomfortable issue can be summarized in the following criticism—a composite of several that I have heard:

Isn’t it true that all the other pocket universes are beyond our horizon? By definition, the horizon separates the world into those places that we can get information from and those places that are absolutely impossible to observe. Doesn’t this imply that the other pockets are,
in principle, unobservable?
If that is so, what difference can they make? Why should we have to appeal to the existence of worlds that have no operational meaning to us? The populated Landscape sounds more like metaphysics than physics.

Because I think this issue is so important, the entire next chapter is devoted to it. Indeed, I could easily write a whole book on the subject of horizons, and I probably will. But for now let’s just contrast two ways of describing the history of the universe. The first way actually corresponds closely to the conventional way of observing the universe. We observe the universe from within, by means of various kinds of telescopes from the surface of the earth. Even if the observations take place from space—on a satellite—the results of the observations are brought back to earth for analysis.

Observations from the earth are limited to things within our horizon. Not only can’t we see anything beyond the horizon, but also nothing behind the horizon can have any influence on our observations. So why not build a theory that restricts attention to a single causal patch? This is a fine pragmatic attitude of which I heartily approve.

What is the history of the universe as seen from a typical observer’s vantage point? A good starting point might be a patch of space trapped in some high-altitude valley. The enormously large vacuum energy leads to repulsive forces that are so violent that even particles like protons are ripped apart almost instantly. That primordial world is extremely inhospitable. It is also very small: the horizon is only a tiny distance away—smaller than a proton radius—and the region accessible to the observer is microscopic, perhaps not much bigger than the Planck length. Obviously no real observer can survive in this environment, but let’s ignore that.

After some time a bubble nucleates and grows, taking over the entire region accessible to the observer. The observer finds himself surrounded by an environment that’s only a little friendlier: the cosmological constant is smaller, and the horizon has grown, giving a bit more room in which to wiggle around. Still, the cosmological constant in the new valley is far too big for comfort. But again a bubble grows, this time resulting in an environment with a somewhat smaller cosmological constant. Such sudden changes may happen several times. The observer sees a series of environments, none suitable for life. Finally a bubble with exactly zero vacuum energy forms—a bubble of supersymmetric vacuum. The bubble evolves to a negatively curved open world and ceases evolving. The probability of passing through one of the extremely rare life-supporting environments, on the way to the graveyard, is extremely small.

But let’s suppose that a bubble of our kind of universe formed before the supersymmetric Landscape was reached. This is a very unlikely event, given how scarce such valleys are, but it can happen. Will life evolve? That depends on exactly how the patch of space got there. One possibility out of many is that it first arrived at the inflationary ledge. That’s good. Inflation leads to a hospitable universe. But if the patch reached our valley from some other direction in the Landscape, all bets are off. If it failed to get hung up for a time on the ledge, the universe would probably never have produced enough heat and particles to later be the stuff of life.

From the perspective of an observer who sees a series of environments ending in the graveyard, the likelihood of life is tiny. But now let’s imagine that we could get outside the universe and see it as a whole. From the perspective of the entire megaverse, the history is not a sequence or series of events. The megaverse description is a more
parallel
view of things—many pocket universes, evolving in parallel. As the megaverse evolves, pocket universes spread over the entire Landscape. It is absolutely certain that some—quite likely a very small fraction—will wind up on the ledge of life. Who cares about all the others that ended badly? Life will form where it can—and only where it can.

Once again a biological analogy may be helpful. Imagine the tree of life—every branch being a species. If you follow the tree outward from the main trunk (bacteria), randomly proceeding at every fork, you will quickly come to extinction. Every species becomes extinct; but if the rate for evolving new species exceeds the extinction rate, the tree continues to spread. If you follow any particular path to extinction, the probability of encountering intelligent life is nil. But it is practically certain that the tree will eventually sprout an intelligent branch if it grows for a long enough time. The parallel view is a much more optimistic view.

Many-Worlds

What if Germany had won World War II? Or what would life be like if the asteroid that killed the dinosaurs sixty-five million years ago had not hit the earth? The idea of a parallel world that took a different course at some critical historical junction is a favorite theme of science-fiction authors. But as real science, I have always dismissed such ideas as frivolous nonsense. But to my surprise I find myself talking and thinking about just such matters. In fact this whole book is about parallel universes: the megaverse is a world of pocket universes that become disconnected—completely out of contact—as they recede beyond one another’s hori-zons.

I am far from the first physicist to seriously entertain the possibility that reality—whatever that means—contains, in addition to our own world of experience, alternate worlds with different history than our own. The subject has been part of an ongoing debate about the interpretation of quantum mechanics. Sometime in the middle 1950s, a young graduate student, Hugh Everett III, put forth a radical reinterpretation of quantum mechanics that he called the
many-worlds interpretation.
Everett’s theory is that at every junction in history the world splits into parallel universes with alternate histories. Although it sounds like fringe speculation, some of the greatest modern physicists have been driven by the weirdness of quantum mechanics to embrace Ever-ett’s ideas—among them, Richard Feynman, Murray Gell-Mann, Steven Weinberg, John Wheeler, and Stephen Hawking. The many-worlds interpretation was the inspiration for the Anthropic Principle when Brandon Carter first formulated it, in 1974.

The many-worlds of Everett seems, at first sight, to be quite a different conception than the eternally inflating megaverse. However, I think the two may really be the same thing. I have emphasized several times that quantum mechanics is not a theory that predicts the future from the past, but rather it determines the probabilities for the possible alternate outcomes of an observation. These probabilities are summarized in the basic mathematical object of quantum mechanics—the
wave function.

If you have learned a little bit about quantum mechanics and know that Schrödinger discovered a wave equation describing electrons, then you have heard of wave functions. I want you to forget all that. Schrödinger’s wave function was a very special case of a much broader concept, and it is this more general idea that I want to concentrate on. At any given time—right now, for example—there are many things that one might observe about the world. I might choose to look out the window just above my desk and see if the moon is up. Or I might plan a two-slit experiment (see chapter 1) and observe the location of a particular spot on the screen. Yet another experiment would involve a single neutron that was prepared a certain time in the past—say, ten minutes ago. You may recall from chapter 1 that a neutron, not bound in a nucleus, is unstable. On the average (but only on the average), in twelve minutes it will decay into a proton, an electron, and an antineutrino. The observation in this case would be to determine whether, after ten minutes, the neutron has decayed or if it is still present in its original form. Each of these experiments or observations has more than one possible outcome. In its most general sense, the wave function is a list of the probabilities for all possible outcomes of all possible observations on the system under consideration. More exactly, it is a list of the square roots of all these probabilities.

The decaying neutron is a good illustration to start with. With a bit of simplification, we can suppose there are only two possible outcomes when we observe the neutron: either it has decayed or it hasn’t. The list of possibilities is a short one, and the wave function has only two entries. We start with the neutron in its undecayed form so that the wave function has value one for the first possibility and zero for the second. In other words initially the probability that the neutron is undecayed is one, while the probability that it has decayed (when we start) is zero. But after a short time, there is a small probability that the neutron has disappeared. The two entries to the wave function have changed from one and zero to something a bit less than one and something a bit more than zero. After about ten minutes the two entries have become equal. Go on for another ten minutes, and the probabilities will be reversed: the probability that the neutron is still intact will be close to zero, and the probability that it has become a proton/ electron/ antineutrino will be up near one. Quantum mechanics contains a set of rules for updating the wave function of a system as time unfolds. In its most general form, the system of interest is everything—the entire observable universe, including the observer doing the observations. Since there may be more than one lump of matter that might be called an observer, the theory must give rise to consistent observations. The wave function contains all of this and in a way that will prove consistent when two observers get together to discuss their findings.

Let’s examine the best known of all thought experiments in physics: the famous (or should I say infamous?) Schrödinger’s cat experiment. Imagine that at noon a cat is placed in a sealed box along with a neutron and a gun. When the neutron decays (randomly), the ejected electron activates a circuit that causes the gun to shoot and kill the cat.

A practitioner of quantum mechanics—call him S—would analyze the experiment by constructing a wave function: a list of the probabilities for the various outcomes. S cannot reasonably take the entire universe into account, so he limits the system to include only those things in the box. At noon only one entry would exist: “The cat is alive in the box with the loaded gun and the neutron.” Then S will do some mathematics analogous to solving Newton’s equations in order to find out what will happen next—say, at 12:10 p.m. But the result is not a prediction of whether the cat will be dead or alive. It is an updating of the wave function, which will now have two entries: “The neutron is intact/ the gun is loaded/ the cat is alive” and “The neutron has decayed/ the gun is empty/ the cat is dead.” The wave function has split into two branches—the dead and alive branches—whose numerical values give the square roots of the probabilities for the two outcomes.

S can open the box and see if the cat is dead or alive. If the cat is alive, then S can throw away the dead-cat branch of the wave function. That branch, if advanced in time, would contain all the information about the world in which the cat was shot, but since S found the cat alive, he has no further need for this information. There is a term for this process of dropping the unobserved branches of the wave function whenever an observation is made. It is called the collapse of the wave function. It is a very convenient trick that allows the physicist to concentrate on only the things that can subsequently be of interest. For example, the live branch has information that may still interest S. If he advances this branch of the wave function a bit more in time, he would be able to determine the probability that the gun would subsequently misfire and shoot S (serves him right). The collapse of the wave function whenever an observation takes place is the primary ingredient of the famous Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics championed by Niels Bohr.

BOOK: The Cosmic Landscape
9.6Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Bruises of the Heart by J. J. Nite
Auschwitz by Laurence Rees
Color Blind by Colby Marshall
Sparks Rise by Alexandra Bracken
Zombie Fallout 2 by Mark Tufo