The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics) (152 page)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
12.65Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

6
     Since we have discussed these points, it is well to consider again the results regarding numbers which confront those who say that numbers are separable substances and first causes of things. If number is an entity and its substance is nothing other than just number,
(15)
as some say, it follows that either (1) there is a first in it and a second, each being different in species—and either (
a
) this is true of the units without exception, and any unit is inassociable with any unit, or (
b
) they are all without exception successive,
(20)
and any of them are associable with any, as they say is the case with mathematical number; for in mathematical number no one unit is in any way different from another. Or (
c
) some units must be associable and some not; e. g. suppose that 2 is first after 1, and then comes 3 and then the rest of the number series, and the units in each number are associable,
(25)
e. g. those in the first 2 are associable with one another, and those in the first 3 with one another, and so with the other numbers; but the units in the ‘2-itself’ are inassociable with those in the ‘3-itself’; and similarly in the case of the other successive numbers.
(30)
And so while mathematical number is counted thus—after 1, 2 (which consists of another 1 besides the former 1), and 3 (which consists of another 1 besides these two), and the other numbers similarly, ideal number is counted thus—after 1, a distinct 2 which does not include the first 1, and a 3 which does not include the 2, and the rest of the number series similarly. Or (2) one kind of number must be like the
first that was named,
23
(35)
one like that which the mathematicians speak of, and that which we have named last
24
must be a third kind.

Again, these kinds of numbers must either be separable from things, or not separable but in objects of perception (not however in the way which we first considered,
25
but in the sense that objects of perception consist of numbers which are present in them)—either one kind and not another, or all of them.
[1080b]

These are of necessity the only ways in which the numbers can exist.
(5)
And of those who say that the 1 is the beginning and substance and element of all things, and that number is formed from the 1 and something else, almost every one has described number in one of these ways; only no one has said
all
the units are inassociable.
(10)
And this has happened reasonably enough; for there can be no way besides those mentioned. Some
26
say both kinds of number exist, that which has a before and after
27
being identical with the Ideas, and mathematical number being different from the Ideas and from sensible things, and both being separable from sensible things; and others
28
say mathematical number alone exists,
(15)
as the first of realities, separate from sensible things. And the Pythagoreans, also, believe in one kind of number—the mathematical; only they say it is not separate but sensible substances are formed out of it. For they construct the whole universe out of numbers—only not numbers consisting of abstract units; they suppose the units to have spatial magnitude.
(20)
But how the first 1 was constructed so as to have magnitude, they seem unable to say.

Another thinker
29
says the first kind of number, that of the Forms, alone exists, and some
30
say mathematical number is identical with this.

The case of lines, planes, and solids is similar. For some think that those which are the objects of mathematics are different from those which come after the Ideas;
31
and of those who express themselves otherwise some speak of the objects of mathematics and in a mathematical way—viz.
(25)
those who do not make the Ideas numbers nor say that Ideas exist;
32
and others speak of the objects of mathematics, but not mathematically; for they say that neither is every spatial magnitude divisible into magnitudes, nor do any two units taken at random make 2.
33
(30)
All who say the 1 is an element and principle of
things suppose numbers to consist of abstract units, except the Pythagoreans; but
they
suppose the numbers to have magnitude, as has been said before.
34
It is clear from this statement, then, in how many ways numbers may be described, and that all the ways have been mentioned; and all these views are impossible, but some perhaps more than others.
(35)

7
     First, then, let us inquire if the units are associable or inassociable, and if inassociable, in which of the two ways we distinguished.
35
For it is possible that any unit is inassociable with any, and it is possible that those in the ‘2-itself’ are inassociable with those in the ‘3-itself’, and, generally, that those in each ideal number are inassociable with those in other ideal numbers.
[1081a]
Now (1) if all units are associable and without difference,
(5)
we get mathematical number—only one kind of number, and the Ideas cannot be the numbers. For what sort of number will man-himself or animal-itself or any other Form be? There is one Idea of each thing, e. g. one of man-himself and another one of animal-itself; but the similar and undifferentiated numbers are infinitely many,
(10)
so that any particular 3 is no more man-himself than any other 3. But if the Ideas are not numbers, neither can they exist at all. For from what principles will the Ideas come? It is number that comes from the 1 and the indefinite dyad,
(15)
and the principles or elements are said to be principles and elements of number, and the Ideas cannot be ranked as either prior or posterior to the numbers.

But (2) if the units are inassociable, and inassociable in the sense that any is inassociable with any other, number of this sort cannot be mathematical number; for mathematical number consists of undifferentiated units, and the truths proved of it suit this character.
(20)
Nor can it be ideal number. For 2 will not proceed immediately from 1 and the indefinite dyad, and be followed by the successive numbers, as they say ‘2, 3, 4’—for the units in the ideal 2 are generated at the same time, whether, as the first holder of the theory
36
said, from unequals (coming into being when these were equalized) or in some other way—since, if one unit is to be prior to the other,
(25)
it will be prior also to the 2 composed of these; for when there is one thing prior and another posterior, the resultant of these will be prior to one and posterior to the other.
37

Again,
(30)
since the 1-itself is first, and then there is a particular 1 which is first among the others and next after the 1-itself, and again a third which is next after the second and next but one after the first 1—so the units must be prior to the numbers after which they are named when we count them; e. g. there will be a third unit in 2 before 3 exists, and a fourth and a fifth in 3 before the numbers 4 and 5 exist.
(35)
—Now none of these thinkers has said the units are inassociable in this way, but according to their principles it is reasonable that they should be so even in this way, though in truth it is impossible.
[1081b]
For it is reasonable both that the units should have priority and posteriority if there is a first unit or first 1, and also that the 2’s should if there is a first 2; for after the first it is reasonable and necessary that there should be a second,
(5)
and if a second, a third, and so with the others successively. (And to say both things at the same time, that a
unit
is first and another unit is second after the ideal 1, and that a 2 is first after it, is impossible.) But they make a first unit or 1, but not also a second and a third, and a first 2, but not also a second and a third.

Clearly,
(10)
also, it is not possible, if all the units are inassociable, that there should be a 2-itself and a 3-itself; and so with the other numbers. For whether the units are undifferentiated or different each from each, number must be counted by addition,
(15)
e. g. 2 by adding another 1 to the one, 3 by adding another 1 to the two, and 4 similarly. This being so, numbers cannot be generated as they generate them, from the 2 and the 1; for 2 becomes part of 3, and 3 of 4,
(20)
and the same happens in the case of the succeeding numbers, but
they
say 4 came from the first 2 and the indefinite 2—which makes it two 2’s
other
than the 2-itself; if not, the 2-itself will be a part of 4 and one other 2 will be added. And similarly 2 will consist of the 1-itself and another 1; but if this is so,
(25)
the other element cannot be an indefinite 2; for it generates one unit, not, as the indefinite 2 does, a definite 2.

Again, besides the 3-itself and the 2-itself how can there be other 3’s and 2’s? And how do they consist of prior and posterior units? All this is absurd and fictitious,
(30)
and there cannot be a first 2 and then a 3-itself. Yet there must, if the 1 and the indefinite dyad are to be the elements. But if the results are impossible, it is also impossible that these are the generating principles.

If the units, then, are differentiated, each from each,
(35)
these results and others similar to these follow of necessity. But (3) if those in different numbers are differentiated, but those in the same number are alone undifferentiated from one another, even so the difficulties that
follow are no less. e. g. in the 10-itself there are ten units, and the 10 is composed both of them and of two 5’s.
[1082a]
But since the 10-itself is not any chance number nor composed of any chance 5’s—or, for that matter, units—the units in this 10 must differ. For if they do not differ, neither will the 5’s of which the 10 consists differ; but since these differ,
(5)
the units also will differ. But if they differ, will there be no other 5’s in the 10 but only these two, or will there be others? If there are not, this is paradoxical; and if there are, what sort of 10 will consist of them? For there is no other 10 in
the
10 but itself.
(10)
But it is actually
necessary
on their view that the 4 should not consist of any chance 2’s; for the indefinite 2, as they say, received the definite 2 and made two 2’s; for its nature was to double what it received.

Again, as to the 2 being an entity apart from its two units,
(15)
and the 3 an entity apart from its three units, how is this possible? Either by one’s sharing in the other, as ‘pale man’ is different from ‘pale’ and ‘man’ (for it shares in these), or when one is a differentia of the other, as ‘man’ is different from ‘animal’ and ‘two-footed’.

Again, some things are one by contact, some by intermixture,
(20)
some by position; none of which can belong to the units of which the 2 or the 3 consists; but as two men are not a unity apart from both, so must it be with the units. And their being indivisible will make no difference to them; for points too are indivisible,
(25)
but yet a pair of them is nothing apart from the two.

But this consequence also we must not forget, that it follows that there are prior and posterior 2’s, and similarly with the other numbers. For let the 2’s in the 4 be simultaneous; yet these are prior to those in the 8,
(30)
and as the 2 generated them, they generated the 4’s in the 8-itself. Therefore if the first 2 is an Idea, these 2’s also will be Ideas of some kind. And the same account applies to the units; for the units in the first 2 generate the four in 4, so that all the units come to be Ideas and an Idea will be composed of Ideas.
(35)
Clearly therefore those things also of which these happen to be the Ideas will be composite, e. g. one might say that animals are composed of animals, if there are Ideas of them.

In general, to differentiate the units in any way is an absurdity and a fiction; and by a fiction I mean a forced statement made to suit a hypothesis.
[1082b]
For neither in quantity nor in quality do we see unit differing from unit,
(5)
and number must be either equal or unequal—all number but especially that which consists of abstract units—so that if one number is neither greater nor less than another, it is equal to it;
but things that are equal and in no wise differentiated we take to be the same when we are speaking of numbers. If not, not even the 2’s in the 10-itself will be undifferentiated,
(10)
though they are equal; for what reason will the man who alleges that they are not differentiated be able to give?

Again, if every unit + another unit makes two, a unit from the 2-itself and one from the 3-itself will make a 2. Now (
a
) this will consist of differentiated units; and (
b
) will it be prior to the 3 or posterior? It rather seems that it must be prior; for one of the units is simultaneous with the 3,
(15)
and the other is simultaneous with the 2. And we, for our part, suppose that in general 1 and 1, whether the things are equal or unequal, is 2, e. g. the good and the bad, or a man and a horse; but those who hold these views say that not even two
units
are 2.

If the number of the 3-itself is not greater than that of the 2,
(20)
this is surprising; and if it
is
greater, clearly there is also a number in it equal to the 2, so that
this
is not different from the 2-itself. But this is not possible, if there is a first and a second number.
38

Nor will the Ideas be numbers. For in this particular point they are right who claim that the units must be different, if there are to be Ideas; as has been said before.
39
(25)
For the Form is unique; but if the units are not different, the 2’s and the 3’s also will not be different. This is also the reason why they must say that when we count thus—‘1, 2’—we do not proceed by adding to the given number; for if we do,
(30)
neither will the numbers be generated from the indefinite dyad, nor can a number be an Idea; for then one Idea will be in another, and all the Forms will be parts of one Form. And so with a view to their hypothesis their statements are right, but as a whole they are wrong; for their view is very destructive, since they will admit that
this
question itself affords some difficulty—whether,
(35)
when we count and say ‘1, 2, 3,’ we count by addition or by separate portions. But we do both; and so it is absurd to reason back from this problem to so great a difference of essence.

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
12.65Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Baroque and Desperate by Tamar Myers
Blackout by Andrew Cope
You'll Say Yes by Tri Amutia, Jovy Lim
A Case of Knives by Candia McWilliam
The Duke Diaries by Sophia Nash
A Gentlewoman's Ravishment by Portia Da Costa
Sovereign Stone by David Wells
Emma Blooms At Last by Naomi King