The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics) (13 page)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
2.48Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

14
     The question arises whether an affirmation finds its contrary in a denial or in another affirmation; whether the proposition ‘every man is just’ finds its contrary in the proposition ‘no man is just’, or in the proposition ‘every man is unjust’. Take the propositions ‘Callias is just’, ‘Callias is not just’, ‘Callias is unjust’; we have to discover which of these form contraries.
(30)

Now if the spoken word corresponds with the judgement of the mind, and if, in thought, that judgement is the contrary of another, which pronounces a contrary fact, in the way, for instance, in which the judgement ‘every man is just’ pronounces a contrary to that pronounced by the judgement ‘every man is unjust’, the same must needs hold good with regard to spoken affirmations.
(35)

But if, in thought, it is not the judgement which pronounces a contrary fact that is the contrary of another, then one affirmation will not find its contrary in another, but rather in the corresponding denial. We must therefore consider which true judgement is the contrary of the false, that which forms the denial of the false judgement or that which affirms the contrary fact.

Let me illustrate. There is a true judgement concerning that which is good,
(40)
that it is good; another, a false judgement, that it is not good; and a third, which is distinct, that it is bad.
[23b]
Which of these two is contrary to the true? And if they are one and the same, which mode of expression forms the contrary?

It is an error to suppose that judgements are to be defined as
contrary in virtue of the fact that they have contrary subjects; for the judgement concerning a good thing, that it is good, and that concerning a bad thing,
(5)
that it is bad, may be one and the same, and whether they are so or not, they both represent the truth. Yet the subjects here are contrary. But judgements are not contrary because they have contrary subjects, but because they are to the contrary effect.

Now if we take the judgement that that which is good is good, and another that it is not good, and if there are at the same time other attributes, which do not and cannot belong to the good, we must nevertheless refuse to treat as the contraries of the true judgement those which opine that some other attribute subsists which does not subsist,
(10)
as also those that opine that some other attribute does not subsist which does subsist, for both these classes of judgement are of unlimited content.

Those judgements must rather be termed contrary to the true judgements, in which error is present. Now these judgements are those which are concerned with the starting points of generation, and generation is the passing from one extreme to its opposite; therefore error is a like transition.

Now that which is good is both good and not bad.
(15)
The first quality is part of its essence, the second accidental; for it is by accident that it is not bad. But if that true judgement is most really true, which concerns the subject’s intrinsic nature, then that false judgement likewise is most really false, which concerns its intrinsic nature. Now the judgement that that which is good is not good is a false judgement concerning its intrinsic nature, the judgement that it is bad is one concerning that which is accidental.
(20)
Thus the judgement which denies the truth of the true judgement is more really false than that which positively asserts the presence of the contrary quality. But it is the man who forms that judgement which is contrary to the true who is most thoroughly deceived, for contraries are among the things which differ most widely within the same class. If then of the two judgements one is contrary to the true judgement, but that which is contradictory is the more truly contrary, then the latter, it seems,
(25)
is the real contrary. The judgement that that which is good is bad is composite. For presumably the man who forms that judgement must at the same time understand that that which is good is not good.

Further, the contradictory is either always the contrary or never; therefore, if it must necessarily be so in all other cases, our conclusion in the case just dealt with would seem to be correct.
(30)
Now where terms have no contrary, that judgement is false, which forms the
negative of the true; for instance, he who thinks a man is not a man forms a false judgement. If then in these cases the negative is the contrary, then the principle is universal in its application.

Again, the judgement that that which is not good is not good is parallel with the judgement that that which is good is good. Besides these there is the judgement that that which is good is not good, parallel with the judgement that that which is not good is good. Let us consider,
(35)
therefore, what would form the contrary of the true judgement that that which is not good is not good. The judgement that it is bad would, of course, fail to meet the case, since two true judgements are never contrary and this judgement might be true at the same time as that with which it is connected. For since some things which are not good are bad, both judgements may be true. Nor is the judgement that it is not bad the contrary, for this too might be true, since both qualities might be predicated of the same subject. It remains, therefore, that of the judgement concerning that which is not good,
(40)
that it is not good, the contrary judgement is that it is good; for this is false.
[24a]
In the same way, moreover, the judgement concerning that which is good, that it is not good, is the contrary of the judgement that it is good.

It is evident that it will make no difference if we universalize the positive judgement, for the universal negative judgement will form the contrary. For instance, the contrary of the judgement that everything that is good is good is that nothing that is good is good.
(5)
For the judgement that that which is good is good, if the subject be understood in a universal sense, is equivalent to the judgement that whatever is good is good, and this is identical with the judgement that everything that is good is good. We may deal similarly with judgements concerning that which is not good.

If therefore this is the rule with judgements, and if spoken affirmations and denials are judgements expressed in words, it is plain that the universal denial is the contrary of the affirmation about the same subject.
[24b]
Thus the propositions ‘everything good is good’, ‘every man is good’, have for their contraries the propositions ‘nothing good is good’, ‘no man is good’. The contradictory propositions,
(5)
on the other hand, are ‘not everything good is good’, ‘not every man is good’.

It is evident, also, that neither true judgements nor true propositions can be contrary the one to the other. For whereas, when two propositions are true, a man may state both at the same time without inconsistency, contrary propositions are those which state contrary conditions, and contrary conditions cannot subsist at one and the same time in the same subject.

1
Cf. 16
a
22–26.

2
Cf.
Poet.
1456
b
11.

3
Cf. 17
b
26–9.

4
Cf. 17
b
29–37.

5
Cf. 16
a
19, 30.

6
Analytica Priora,
51
b
36–52
a
17.

7
Cf. 17
b
38.

8
Topica,
viii. 7.

ANALYTICA PRIORA
Translated by A. J. Jenkinson

CONTENTS

BOOK I

A.
Structure of the Syllogism.

1. P
RELIMINARY
D
ISCUSSIONS
.

   
CHAPTER

  
1.
   Subject and scope of the Analytics. Certain definitions and divisions.

  
2.
   Conversion of pure propositions.

  
3.
   Conversion of necessary and contingent propositions.

2. E
XPOSITION OF THE
T
HREE
F
IGURES
.

  
4.
   Pure syllogisms in the first figure.

  
5.
   Pure syllogisms in the second figure.

  
6.
   Pure syllogisms in the third figure.

  
7.
   Common properties of the three figures.

[Chapters 8–12 omitted.]

13.
   Preliminary discussion of the contingent.

[Chapters 14–22 omitted.]

3. S
UPPLEMENTARY
D
ISCUSSIONS
.

23.
   Every syllogism is in one of the three figures, is completed through the first figure, and reducible to a universal mood of the first figure.

24.
   Quality and quantity of the premisses of the syllogism.

25.
   Number of the terms, propositions, and conclusions.

26.
   The kinds of proposition to be established or disproved in each figure.

B.
Mode of discovery of arguments.

1. G
ENERAL
.

27.
   Rules for categorical syllogisms, applicable to all problems.

28.
   Rules for categorical syllogisms, peculiar to different problems.

29.
   Rules for
reductio ad impossibile,
hypothetical syllogisms, and modal syllogisms.

30.
 

2. P
ROPER TO THE
S
EVERAL
S
CIENCES AND
A
RTS
.

31.
 

3. D
IVISION
.

C.
Analysis
(1)
of arguments into figures and moods of syllogism.

         [Chapters 32–46 omitted.]

BOOK II

Properties and defects of syllogism; arguments akin to syllogism.

A. P
ROPERTIES
.

         [Chapters 1–15 omitted.]

B. D
EFECTS
.

16.
   
Petitio principii.

17.
   False Cause.

18.
   Falsity of conclusion due to falsity in one or more premisses.

19.
   How to impede opposing arguments and conceal one’s own.

20.
   When refutation is possible.

21.
   Error.

C. A
RGUMENTS
A
KIN TO
S
YLLOGISM
.

22.
   Rules for conversion and for the comparison of desirable and undesirable objects.

23.
   Induction.

24.
   Example.

25.
   Reduction.

26.
   Objection.

27.
   Enthymeme.

ANALYTICA PRIORA

(Prior Analytics)

BOOK I

1
     We must first state the subject of our inquiry and the faculty to which it belongs:
(10)
its subject is demonstration and the faculty that carries it out demonstrative science.
[24a]
We must next define a premiss, a term, and a syllogism, and the nature of a perfect and of an imperfect syllogism; and after that, the inclusion or non-inclusion of one term in another as in a whole, and what we mean by predicating one term of all, or none, of another.
(15)

A premiss then is a sentence affirming or denying one thing of another. This is either universal or particular or indefinite. By universal I mean the statement that something belongs to all or none of something else; by particular that it belongs to some or not to some or not to all; by indefinite that it does or does not belong, without any mark to show whether it is universal or particular,
(20)
e. g. ‘contraries are subjects of the same science’, or ‘pleasure is not good’. The demonstrative premiss differs from the dialectical, because the demonstrative premiss is the assertion of one of two contradictory statements (the demonstrator does not ask for his premiss, but lays it down), whereas the dialectical premiss depends on the adversary’s choice between two contradictories.
(25)
But this will make no difference to the production of a syllogism in either case; for both the demonstrator and the dialectician argue syllogistically after stating that something does or does not belong to something else. Therefore a syllogistic premiss without qualification will be an affirmation or denial of something concerning something else in the way we have described; it will be demonstrative, if it is true and obtained through the first principles of its science; while a dialectical premiss is the giving of a choice between two contradictories,
(30)
when a man is proceeding by question,
(10)
but when he is syllogizing it is the assertion of that which is apparent and generally admitted, as has been said in the
Topics
.
1
[24b]
The nature then of a premiss and the difference between syllogistic, demonstrative, and dialectical premisses, may be taken as sufficiently
defined by us in relation to our present need,
(15)
but will be stated accurately in the sequel.
2

I call that a term into which the premiss is resolved, i. e. both the predicate and that of which it is predicated, ‘being’ being added and ‘not being’ removed, or vice versa.

A syllogism is discourse in which, certain things being stated, something other than what is stated follows of necessity from their being so.
(20)
I mean by the last phrase that they produce the consequence, and by this, that no further term is required from without in order to make the consequence necessary.

I call that a perfect syllogism which needs nothing other than what has been stated to make plain what necessarily follows; a syllogism is imperfect, if it needs either one or more propositions,
(25)
which are indeed the necessary consequences of the terms set down, but have not been expressly stated as premisses.

That one term should be included in another as in a whole is the same as for the other to be predicated of all of the first. And we say that one term is predicated of all of another, whenever no instance of the subject can be found of which the other term cannot be asserted: ‘to be predicated of none’ must be understood in the same way.
(30)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
2.48Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

o f31e4a444fa175b2 by deba schrott
The Templar Archive by James Becker
Fallen Angels by Patricia Hickman
For Lovers Only by Alex Hairston
Nicholas: Lord of Secrets by Grace Burrowes
The Trinity by LaBounty, David
Arcane Solutions by Gayla Drummond