The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics) (70 page)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
9.59Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

6
     Further, neither that which moves towards nor that which moves away from the centre can be infinite. For the upward and downward motions are contraries and are therefore motions towards contrary places. But if one of a pair of contraries is determinate, the other must be determinate also.
(10)
Now the centre is determined; for, from whatever point the body which sinks to the bottom starts its downward motion, it cannot go farther than the centre. The centre, therefore, being determinate, the upper place must also be determinate. But if these two places are determined and finite,
(15)
the corresponding bodies must also be finite. Further, if up and down are determinate, the intermediate place is also necessarily determinate. For, if it is indeterminate, the movement within it will be infinite; and that we have already shown to be an impossibility.
12
The middle region then is determinate, and consequently any body which either is in it, or might be in it, is determinate. But the bodies which move up and down may be in it,
(20)
since the one moves naturally away from the centre and the other towards it.

From this alone it is clear that an infinite body is an impossibility; but there is a further point. If there is no such thing as infinite weight, then it follows that none of these bodies can be infinite. For the supposed infinite body would have to be infinite in weight.
(25)
(The same argument applies to lightness: for as the one supposition involves infinite
weight, so the infinity of the body which rises to the surface involves infinite lightness.) This is proved as follows. Assume the weight to be finite, and take an infinite body,
AB,
of the weight
C.
(30)
Subtract from the infinite body a finite mass,
BD,
the weight of which shall be
E. E
then is less than
C,
since it is the weight of a lesser mass. Suppose then that the smaller goes into the greater a certain number of times, and take
BF
bearing the same proportion to
BD
which the greater weight bears to the smaller.
[273b]
For you may subtract as much as you please from an infinite. If now the masses are proportionate to the weights, and the lesser weight is that of the lesser mass,
(5)
the greater must be that of the greater. The weights, therefore, of the finite and of the infinite body are equal. Again, if the weight of a greater body is greater than that of a less, the weight of
GB
will be greater than that of
FB;
and thus the weight of the finite body is greater than that of the infinite. And, further, the weight of unequal masses will be the same,
(10)
since the infinite and the finite cannot be equal. It does not matter whether the weights are commensurable or not. If (
a
) they are
incommensurable
the same reasoning holds. For instance, suppose
E
multiplied by three is rather more than
C:
the weight of three masses of the full size of
BD
will be greater than
C.
(15)
We thus arrive at the same impossibility as before. Again (
b
) we may assume weights which are
commensurate;
for it makes no difference whether we begin with the weight or with the mass. For example, assume the weight
E
to be commensurate with
C,
and take from the infinite mass a part
BD
of weight
E.
(20)
Then let a mass
BF
be taken having the same proportion to
BD
which the two weights have to one another. (For the mass being infinite you may subtract from it as much as you please.) These assumed bodies will be commensurate in mass and in weight alike. Nor again does it make any difference to our demonstration whether the total mass has its weight equally or unequally distributed.
(25)
For it must always be possible to take from the infinite mass a body of equal weight to
BD
by diminishing or increasing the size of the section to the necessary extent.

From what we have said, then, it is clear that the weight of the infinite body cannot be finite. It must then be infinite. We have therefore only to show this to be impossible in order to prove an infinite body impossible.
(30)
But the impossibility of infinite weight can be shown in the following way. A given weight moves a given distance in a given time; a weight which is as great and more moves the same distance in a less time, the times being in inverse proportion to the weights.
[274a]
For instance, if one weight is twice another, it will take half as long over a given movement. Further, a finite weight traverses any finite
distance in a finite time. It necessarily follows from this that infinite weight, if there is such a thing, being, on the one hand, as great and more than as great as the finite, will move accordingly, but being,
(5)
on the other hand, compelled to move in a time inversely proportionate to its greatness, cannot move at all. The time should be less in proportion as the weight is greater. But there is no proportion between the infinite and the finite: proportion can only hold between a less and a greater
finite
time. And though you may say that the time of the movement can be continually diminished, yet there is no minimum. Nor, if there were, would it help us.
(10)
For some finite body could have been found greater than the given finite in the same proportion which is supposed to hold between the infinite and the given finite; so that an infinite and a finite weight must have traversed an equal distance in equal time. But that is impossible. Again, whatever the time, so long as it is finite, in which the infinite performs the motion,
(15)
a finite weight must necessarily move a certain finite distance in that same time. Infinite weight is therefore impossible, and the same reasoning applies also to infinite lightness. Bodies then of infinite weight and of infinite lightness are equally impossible.

That there is no infinite body may be shown, as we have shown it, by a detailed consideration of the various cases. But it may also be shown universally,
(20)
not only by such reasoning as we advanced in our discussion of principles
13
(though in that passage we have already determined universally the sense in which the existence of an infinite is to be asserted or denied), but also suitably to our present purpose in the following way. That will lead us to a further question. Even if the total mass is not infinite, it may yet be great enough to admit a plurality of universes.
(25)
The question might possibly be raised whether there is any obstacle to our believing that there are other universes composed on the pattern of our own, more than one, though stopping short of infinity. First, however, let us treat of the infinite universally.

7
     Every body must necessarily be either finite or infinite,
(30)
and if infinite, either of similar or of dissimilar parts. If its parts are
dissimilar,
they must represent either a finite or an infinite number of kinds. That the kinds cannot be
infinite
is evident, if our original presuppositions remain unchallenged.
[274b]
For the primary movements being finite in number, the kinds of simple body are necessarily also finite, since the movement of a simple body is simple, and the simple movements are finite, and every natural body must always have its proper motion. Now if the infinite body is to be composed of a
finite
number of kinds,
(5)
then each of its parts must necessarily be infinite in quantity, that is to say, the water, fire, &c., which compose it. But this is impossible, because, as we have already shown, infinite weight and lightness do not exist. Moreover it would be necessary also that their places should be infinite in extent,
(10)
so that the movements too of all these bodies would be infinite. But this is not possible, if we are to hold to the truth of our original presuppositions and to the view that neither that which moves downward, nor, by the same reasoning, that which moves upward, can prolong its movement to infinity. For it is true in regard to quality, quantity, and place alike that any process of change is impossible which can have no end.
(15)
I mean that if it is impossible for a thing to have come to be white, or a cubit long, or in Egypt, it is also impossible for it to be in process of coming to be any of these. It is thus impossible for a thing to be moving to a place at which in its motion it can never by any possibility arrive. Again, suppose the body to exist in dispersion, it may be maintained none the less that the total of all these scattered particles, say, of fire,
(20)
is infinite. But body we saw to be that which has extension every way. How can there be several dissimilar elements, each infinite? Each would have to be infinitely extended every way.

It is no more conceivable, again, that the infinite should exist as a whole of
similar
parts. For, in the first place, there is no other [straight] movement beyond those mentioned: we must therefore give it one of them.
(25)
And if so, we shall have to admit either infinite weight or infinite lightness. Nor, secondly, could the body whose movement is circular be infinite, since it is impossible for the infinite to move in a circle. This, indeed, would be as good as saying that the heavens are infinite, which we have shown to be impossible.

Moreover,
(30)
in general, it is impossible that the infinite should move at all. If it did, it would move either naturally or by constraint: and if by constraint, it possesses also a natural motion, that is to say, there is another place, infinite like itself, to which it will move. But that is impossible.

That in general it is impossible for the infinite to be acted upon by the finite or to act upon it may be shown as follows.

[275a]
<1.
The infinite cannot be acted upon by the finite.
> Let
A
be an infinite,
B
a finite,
C
the time of a given movement produced by one in the other. Suppose, then, that
A
was heated, or impelled, or modified in any way, or caused to undergo any sort of movement whatever, by
B
in the time
C.
Let
D
be less than
B;
and,
(5)
assuming that a lesser agent moves a lesser patient in an equal time, call the quantity thus modified by
D, E.
Then, as
D
is to
B,
so is
E
to some finite
quantum. We assume that the alteration of equal by equal takes equal time, and the alteration of less by less or of greater by greater takes the same time, if the quantity of the patient is such as to keep the proportion which obtains between the agents, greater and less. If so,
(10)
no movement can be caused in the infinite by any finite agent in any time whatever. For a less agent will produce that movement in a less patient in an equal time, and the proportionate equivalent of that patient will be a finite quantity, since no proportion holds between finite and infinite.

<2.
The infinite cannot act upon the finite.
> Nor, again, can the infinite produce a movement in the finite in any time whatever.
(15)
Let
A
be an infinite,
B
14
a finite,
C
the time of action. In the time
C, D
will produce that motion in a patient less than
B,
say
F.
Then take
E,
bearing the same proportion to
D
as the whole
BF
bears to
F. E
will produce the motion in
BF
in the time
C.
Thus the finite and the infinite effect the same alteration in equal times.
(20)
But this is impossible; for the assumption is that the greater effects it in a shorter time. It will be the same with any time that can be taken, so that there will be no time in which the infinite can effect this movement. And, as to infinite time, in that nothing can move another or be moved by it. For such time has no limit, while the action and reaction have.

<3.
There is no interaction between infinites.
> Nor can infinite be acted upon in any way by infinite. Let
A
and
B
be infinites,
CD
being the time of the action of
A
upon
B.
(25)
Now the whole
B
was modified in a certain time, and the part of this infinite,
E,
cannot be so modified in the same time, since we assume that a less quantity makes the movemnet in a less time. Let
E
then, when acted upon by
A,
complete the movement in the time
D.
Then, as
D
is to
CD,
so is
E
to some finite part of
B.
(30)
This part dill necessarily be moved by
A
in the time
CD.
For we suppose that the same agent produces a given effect on a greater and a smaller mass in longer and shorter times, the times and masses varying proportionately.
[275b]
There is thus no finite time in which infinites can move one another. Is their time then infinite? No, for infinite time has no end, but the movement communicated has.

If therefore every perceptible body possesses the power of acting or of being acted upon,
(5)
or both of these, it is impossible that an infinite body should be perceptible. All bodies, however, that occupy place are perceptible. There is therefore no infinite body beyond the heaven. Nor again is there anything of limited extent beyond it.
And so beyond the heaven there is no body at all.
(10)
For if you suppose it an object of intelligence, it will be in a place—since place is what ‘within’ and ‘beyond’ denote—and therefore an object of perception. But nothing that is not in a place is perceptible.

The question may also be examined in the light of more general considerations as follows. The infinite, considered as a whole of similar parts, cannot, on the one hand, move in a circle.
(15)
For there is no centre of the infinite, and that which moves in a circle moves about the centre. Nor again can the infinite move in a straight line. For there would have to be another place infinite like itself to be the goal of its natural movement and another, equally great, for the goal of its unnatural movement. Moreover, whether its rectilinear movement is natural or constrained, in either case the force which causes its motion will have to be infinite.
(20)
For infinite force is force of an infinite body, and of an infinite body the force is infinite. So the motive body also will be infinite. (The proof of this is given in our discussion of movement,
15
where it is shown that no finite thing possesses infinite power, and no infinite thing finite power.) If then that which moves naturally can also move unnaturally, there will be two infinites,
(25)
one which causes, and another which exhibits the latter motion. Again, what is it that moves the infinite? If it moves itself, it must be animate. But how can it possibly be conceived as an infinite animal? And if there is something else that moves it, there will be two infinites, that which moves and that which is moved, differing in their form and power.

If the whole is not continuous,
(30)
but exists, as Democritus and Leucippus think, in the form of parts separated by void, there must necessarily be one movement of all the multitude.
[276a]
They are distinguished, we are told, from one another by their figures; but their nature is one, like many pieces of gold separated from one another. But each piece must, as we assert, have the same motion. For a single clod moves to the same place as the whole mass of earth, and a spark to the same place as the whole mass of fire. So that if it be weight that all possess,
(5)
no body is, strictly speaking, light; and if lightness be universal, none is heavy. Moreover, whatever possesses weight or lightness will have its place either at one of the extremes or in the middle region. But this is impossible while the world is conceived as infinite. And, generally, that which has no centre or extreme limit,
(10)
no up or down, gives the bodies no place for their motion; and without that movement is impossible. A thing must move either naturally or unnaturally, and the two movements are determined by the proper
and alien places. Again, a place in which a thing rests or to which it moves unnaturally, must be the natural place for some other body,
(15)
as experience shows. Necessarily, therefore, not everything possesses weight or lightness, but some things do and some do not. From these arguments then it is clear that the body of the universe is not infinite.

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
9.59Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Look Both Ways by Carol J. Perry
Royce by Kathi S. Barton
The Strength of His Hand by Austin, Lynn
A Time to Die by Lurlene McDaniel
THE LAST GOOD WAR: A Novel by Wonnacott, Paul
Cowgirl Come Home by Debra Salonen - Big Sky Mavericks 03 - Cowgirl Come Home
The Horror in the Museum by H. P. Lovecraft
Bane by Viola Grace