The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics) (27 page)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
3.36Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

22
     In the case of predicates constituting the essential nature of a thing, it clearly terminates, seeing that if definition is possible, or in other words, if essential form is knowable, and an infinite series cannot be traversed, predicates constituting a thing’s essential nature must be finite in number.
26
But as regards predicates generally we have the following prefatory remarks to make.
[83a]
(1) We can affirm without falsehood ‘the white (thing) is walking’, and ‘that big (thing) is a log’; or again, ‘the log is big’, and ‘the man walks’. But
the affirmation differs in the two cases. When I affirm ‘the white is a log’,
(5)
I mean that something which happens to be white is a log—not that white is the substratum in which log inheres, for it was not
qua
white or
qua
a species of white that the white (thing) came to be a log, and the white (thing) is consequently not a log except incidentally. On the other hand, when I affirm ‘the log is white’, I do not mean that something else, which happens also to be a log,
(10)
is white (as I should if I said ‘the musician is white’, which would mean ‘the man who happens also to be a musician is white’); on the contrary, log is here the substratum—the substratum which actually came to be white, and did so
qua
wood or
qua
a species of wood and
qua
nothing else.

If we must lay down a rule, let us entitle the latter kind of statement predication,
(15)
and the former not predication at all, or not strict but accidental predication. ‘White’ and ‘log’ will thus serve as types respectively of predicate and subject.

We shall assume, then, that the predicate is invariably predicated strictly and not accidentally of the subject,
(20)
for on such predication demonstrations depend for their force. It follows from this that when a single attribute is predicated of a single subject, the predicate must affirm of the subject either some element constituting its essential nature, or that it is in some way qualified, quantified, essentially related, active, passive, placed, or dated.
27

(2) Predicates which signify substance signify that the subject is identical with the predicate or with a species of the predicate.
(25)
Predicates not signifying substance which are predicated of a subject not identical with themselves or with a species of themselves are accidental or coincidental; e. g. white is a coincident of man, seeing that man is not identical with white or a species of white,
(30)
but rather with animal, since man
is
identical with a species of animal. These predicates which do not signify substance must be predicates of some other subject, and nothing can be white which is not also other than white. The Forms we can dispense with, for they are mere sound without sense; and even if there are such things, they are not relevant
to our discussion, since demonstrations are concerned with predicates such as we have defined.
28
(35)

(3) If
A
is a quality of
B, B
cannot be a quality of
A
—a quality of a quality. Therefore
A
and
B
cannot be predicated reciprocally of one another in strict predication: they can be affirmed without falsehood of one another, but not genuinely predicated of each other.
29
For one alternative is that they should be substantially predicated of one another, i. e.
B
would become the genus or differentia of
A
—the predicate now become subject.
[83b]
But it has been shown that in these substantial predications neither the ascending predicates nor the descending subjects form an infinite series; e. g. neither the series, man is biped, biped is animal, &c., nor the series predicating animal of man, man of Callias, Callias of a further subject as an element of its essential nature, is infinite. For all such substance is definable,
(5)
and an infinite series cannot be traversed in thought: consequently neither the ascent nor the descent is infinite, since a substance whose predicates were infinite would not be definable. Hence they will not be predicated each as the genus of the other; for this would equate a genus with one of its own species. Nor (the other alternative) can a
quale
be reciprocally predicated of a
quale,
(10)
nor any term belonging to an adjectival category of another such term, except by accidental predication; for all such predicates are coincidents and are predicated of substances.
30
On the other hand—in proof of the impossibility of an infinite ascending series—every predication displays the subject as somehow qualified or quantified or as characterized under one of the other adjectival categories, or else is an element in its substantial nature: these latter are limited in number,
(15)
and the number of the widest kinds under which predications fall is also limited, for every
predication must exhibit its subject as somehow qualified, quantified, essentially related, acting or suffering, or in some place or at some time.
31

I assume first that predication implies a single subject and a single attribute, and secondly that predicates which are not substantial are not predicated of one another. We assume this because such predicates are all coincidents, and though some are essential coincidents,
(20)
others of a different type, yet we maintain that all of them alike are predicated of some substratum and that a coincident is never a substratum—since we do not class as a coincident anything which does not owe its designation to its being something other than itself, but always hold that any coincident is predicated of some substratum other than itself, and that another group of coincidents may have a different substratum. Subject to these assumptions then,
(25)
neither the ascending nor the descending series of predication in which a single attribute is predicated of a single subject is infinite.
32
For the subjects of which coincidents are predicated are as many as the constitutive elements of each individual substance, and these we have seen are not infinite in number, while in the ascending series are contained those constitutive elements with their coincidents—both of which are finite.
33
We conclude that there is a given subject <
D
> of which some attribute <
C
> is primarily predicable; that there must be an attribute <
B
> primarily predicable of the first attribute,
(30)
and that the series must end with a term <
A.
> not predicable
able of any term prior to the last subject of which it was predicated <
B
>, and of which no term prior to it is predicable.
34

The argument we have given is one of the so-called proofs; an alternative proof follows. Predicates so related to their subjects that there are other predicates prior to them predicable of those subjects are demonstrable; but of demonstrable propositions one cannot have something better than knowledge, nor can one know them without demonstration.
(35)
Secondly, if a consequent is only known through an antecedent (viz. premisses prior to it) and we neither know this antecedent nor have something better than knowledge of it, then we shall not have scientific knowledge of the consequent. Therefore, if it is possible through demonstration to know anything without qualification and not merely as dependent on the acceptance of certain premisses—i. e. hypothetically—the series of intermediate predications must terminate. If it does not terminate, and beyond any predicate taken as higher than another there remains another still higher, then every predicate is demonstrable.
[84a]
Consequently, since these demonstrable predicates are infinite in number and therefore cannot
not be traversed, we shall
not
know them by demonstration. If, therefore, we have not something better than knowledge of them,
(5)
we cannot through demonstration have unqualified but only hypothetical science of anything.
35

As dialectical proofs of our contention these may carry conviction, but an analytic process will show more briefly that neither the ascent nor the descent of predication can be infinite in the demonstrative sciences which are the object of our investigation.
(10)
Demonstration proves the inherence of essential attributes in things. Now attributes may be essential for two reasons: either because they are elements in the essential nature of their subjects, or because their subjects are elements in their essential nature. An example of the latter is odd as an attribute of number—though it is number’s attribute,
(15)
yet number itself is an element in the definition of odd; of the former, multiplicity or the indivisible, which are elements in the definition of number. In neither kind of attribution can the terms be infinite. They are not infinite where each is related to the term below it as odd is to number, for this would mean the inherence in odd of another attribute of odd in whose nature odd was an essential element: but then number will be an ultimate subject of the whole infinite chain of attributes,
(20)
and be an element in the definition of each of them. Hence, since an infinity of attributes such as contain their subject in their definition cannot inhere in a single thing, the ascending series is equally finite.
36
Note, moreover, that all such attributes must so inhere in the ultimate subject—e. g. its attributes in number and number in them—as to be commensurate with the subject and not of wider extent.
(25)
Attributes which are essential elements in the nature of their subjects are equally finite: otherwise definition would
be impossible. Hence, if all the attributes predicated are essential and these cannot be infinite, the ascending series will terminate, and consequently the descending series too.
37

If this is so, it follows that the intermediates between any two terms are also always limited in number.
38
An immediately obvious consequence of this is that demonstrations necessarily involve basic truths,
(30)
and that the contention of some—referred to at the outset—that all truths are demonstrable is mistaken. For if there are basic truths, (
a
) not all truths are demonstrable, and (
b
) an infinite regress is impossible; since if either (
a
) or (
b
) were not a fact, it would mean that no interval was immediate and indivisible, but that all intervals were divisible. This is true because a conclusion is demonstrated by the interposition,
(35)
not the apposition, of a fresh term. If such interposition could continue to infinity there might be an infinite number of terms between any two terms; but this is impossible if both the ascending and descending series of predication terminate; and of this fact, which before was shown dialectically, analytic proof has now been given.
39
[84b]

23
     It is an evident corollary of these conclusions that if the same attribute
A
inheres in two terms
C
and
D
predicable either not at all, or not of all instances, of one another, it does not always belong to them in virtue of a common middle term.
(5)
Isosceles and scalene possess the attribute of having their angles equal to two right angles in virtue of a common middle; for they possess it in so far as they are both a certain kind of figure, and not in so far as they differ from one another. But this is not always the case; for, were it so, if we take
B
as the common middle in virtue of which
A
inheres in
C
and
D,
clearly
B
would inhere in
C
and
D
through a second common middle,
(10)
and this in turn would inhere in
C
and
D
through a third, so that between two terms an infinity of intermediates would fall—an impossibility. Thus it need not always be in virtue of a common middle term that a single attribute inheres in several subjects,
(15)
since there must be immediate intervals. Yet if the attribute to be proved common to two subjects is to be one of their essential attributes, the middle terms involved must be within one subject genus and be derived from the same group of immediate premisses; for we have seen that processes of proof cannot pass from one genus to another.
40

It is also clear that when
A
inheres in
B,
this can be demonstrated if there is a middle term.
(20)
Further, the ‘elements’ of such a conclusion are the premisses containing the middle in question, and they are identical in number with the middle terms, seeing that the immediate propositions—or at least such immediate propositions as are universal—are the ‘elements’. If, on the other hand, there is no middle term, demonstration ceases to be possible: we are on the way to the basic truths. Similarly if
A
does not inhere in
B,
(25)
this can be demonstrated if there is a middle term or a term prior to
B
in which
A
does not inhere: otherwise there is no demonstration and a basic truth is reached. There are, moreover, as many ‘elements’ of the demonstrated conclusion as there are middle terms, since it is propositions containing these middle terms that are the basic premisses on which the demonstration rests; and as there are some indemonstrable basic truths asserting that ‘this is that’ or that ‘this inheres in that’,
(30)
so there are others denying that ‘this is that’ or that ‘this inheres in that’—in fact some basic truths will affirm and some will deny being.

When we are to prove a conclusion, we must take a primary essential predicate—suppose it
C
—of the subject
B,
and then suppose
A
similarly predicable of
C.
If we proceed in this manner, no proposition or attribute which falls beyond
A
is admitted in the proof: the interval is constantly condensed until subject and predicate become indivisible,
(35)
i. e. one. We have our unit when the premiss becomes immediate, since the immediate premiss alone is a single premiss in the unqualified sense of ‘single’. And as in other spheres the basic element is simple but not identical in all—in a system of weight it is the mina, in music the quarter-tone, and so on—so in syllogism the unit is an immediate premiss, and in the knowledge that demonstration gives it is an intuition.
[85a]
In syllogisms, then, which prove the inherence of an attribute, nothing falls outside the major term. In the case of negative syllogisms on the other hand, (1) in
the first figure nothing falls outside the major term whose inherence is in question; e. g. to prove through a middle
C
that
A
does not inhere in
B
the premisses required are, all
B
is
C,
no
C
is
A.
(5)
Then if it has to be proved that no
C
is
A,
a middle must be found between
A
and
C;
and this procedure will never vary.

(2) If we have to show that
E
is not
D
by means of the premisses, all
D
is
C;
no
E,
or not all
E,
41
is
C;
then the middle will never fall beyond
E,
and
E
is the subject of which
D
is to be denied in the conclusion.

(3) In the third figure the middle will never fall beyond the limits of the subject and the attribute denied of it.
(10)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
3.36Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Half Moon Bay by Helene Young
Abruption by Riley Mackenzie
Seeing Your Face Again by Jerry S. Eicher
Witch Bane by Tim Marquitz
The Last Witness by John Matthews
Lethal Dose of Love by Cindy Davis
The Last Empty Places by Peter Stark
Every Woman Needs a Wife by Naleighna Kai