The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics) (177 page)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
4.56Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

8
     The self-indulgent man, as was said,
30
is not apt to repent; for he stands by his choice; but any incontinent man is likely to repent.
(30)
This is why the position is not as it was expressed in the formulation of the problem,
31
but the self-indulgent man is incurable and the incontinent man curable; for wickedness is like a disease such as dropsy or consumption, while incontinence is like epilepsy; the former is a permanent, the latter an intermittent badness.
(35)
And generally incontinence and vice are different in kind; vice is unconscious of itself, incontinence is not (of incontinent men themselves, those who become temporarily beside themselves are better than those who have the rational principle but do not abide by it, since the latter are defeated by a weaker passion, and do not act without previous deliberation like the others); for the incontinent man is like the people who get drunk quickly and on little wine, i. e. on less than most people.
[1151a]

Evidently, then, incontinence is not vice (though perhaps it is so in a qualified sense); for incontinence is contrary to choice while vice is in accordance with choice; not but what they are similar in respect of the actions they lead to; as in the saying of Demodocus about the Milesians,
(5)
‘the Milesians are not without sense, but they do the things that senseless people do’, so too incontinent people are not criminal,
(10)
but they will do criminal acts.

Now, since the incontinent man is apt to pursue, not on conviction, bodily pleasures that are excessive and contrary to the right rule, while the self-indulgent man is convinced because he is the sort of man to pursue them, it is on the contrary the former that is easily persuaded to change his mind,
(15)
while the latter is not. For virtue and vice respectively preserve and destroy the first principle, and in actions the final cause is the first principle, as the hypotheses
32
are in mathematics; neither in that case is it argument that teaches the first principles, nor is it so here—virtue either natural or produced by habituation is what teaches right opinion about the first principle. Such a man as this, then, is temperate; his contrary is the self-indulgent.
(20)

But there is a sort of man who is carried away as a result of passion and contrary to the right rule—a man whom passion masters so that he does not act according to the right rule, but does not master to the extent of making him ready to believe that he ought to pursue such pleasures without reserve; this is the incontinent man,
(25)
who is better than the self-indulgent man, and not bad without qualification; for the best thing in him, the first principle, is preserved. And contrary to him is another kind of man, he who abides by his convictions and is not carried away, at least as a result of passion. It is evident from these considerations that the latter is a good state and the former a bad one.

9
     Is the man continent who abides by any and every rule and any and every choice, or the man who abides by the right choice,
(30)
and is he incontinent who abandons any and every choice and any and every rule, or he who abandons the rule that is not false and the choice that is right; this is how we put it before in our statement of the problem.
33
Or is it incidentally any and every choice but
per se
the true rule and the right choice by which the one abides and the other does not? If any one chooses or pursues this for the sake of that,
(35)
per se
he pursues and chooses the latter, but incidentally the former.
[1151b]
But when we speak without qualification we mean what is
per se
. Therefore in a sense the one abides by, and the other abandons, any and every opinion; but without qualification, the true opinion.

There are some who are apt to abide by their opinion,
(5)
who are called strong-headed, viz. those who are hard to persuade in the first instance and are not easily persuaded to change; these have in them something like the continent man, as the prodigal is in a way like the liberal man and the rash man like the confident man; but they are
different in many respects. For it is to passion and appetite that the one will not yield, since on occasion the continent man
will
be easy to persuade; but it is to argument that the others refuse to yield,
(10)
for they do form appetites and many of them are led by their pleasures. Now the people who are strong-headed are the opinionated, the ignorant, and the boorish—the opinionated being influenced by pleasure and pain; for they delight in the victory they gain if they are not persuaded to change, and are pained if their decisions become null and void as decrees sometimes do; so that they are liker the incontinent than the continent man.
(15)

But there are some who fail to abide by their resolutions, not as a result of incontinence, e. g. Neoptolemus in Sophocles’
Philoctetes
; yet it was for the sake of pleasure that he did not stand fast—but a noble pleasure; for telling the truth was noble to him,
(20)
but he had been persuaded by Odysseus to tell the lie. For not every one who does anything for the sake of pleasure is either self-indulgent or bad or incontinent, but he who does it for a disgraceful pleasure.

Since there is also a sort of man who takes less delight than he should in bodily things, and does not abide by the rule, he who is intermediate between him and the incontinent man is the continent man; for the incontinent man fails to abide by the rule because he delights too much in them,
(25)
and this man because he delights in them too little; while the continent man abides by the rule and does not change on either account. Now if continence is good, both the contrary states must be bad, as they actually appear to be; but because the other extreme is seen in few people and seldom,
(30)
as temperance is thought to be contrary only to self-indulgence, so is continence to incontinence.

Since many names are applied analogically, it is by analogy that we have come to speak of the ‘continence’ of the temperate man; for both the continent man and the temperate man are such as to do nothing contrary to the rule for the sake of the bodily pleasures,
(35)
but the former has and the latter has not bad appetites, and the latter is such as not to feel pleasure contrary to the rule, while the former is such as to feel pleasure but not to be led by it.
[1152a]
And the incontinent and the self-indulgent man are also like another; they are different,
(5)
but both pursue bodily pleasures—the latter, however, also thinking that he ought to do so, while the former does not think this.

10
     Nor can the same man have practical wisdom and be incontinent; for it has been shown
34
that a man is at the same time practically wise,
and good in respect of character. Further, a man has practical wisdom not by knowing only but by being able to act; but the incontinent man is unable to act—there is, however, nothing to prevent a
clever
man from being incontinent; this is why it is sometimes actually thought that some people have practical wisdom but are incontinent,
(10)
viz. because cleverness and practical wisdom differ in the way we have described in our first discussions,
35
and are near together in respect of their reasoning, but differ in respect of their purpose—nor yet is the incontinent man like the man who knows and is contemplating a truth,
(15)
but like the man who is asleep or drunk. And he acts willingly (for he acts in a sense with knowledge both of what he does and of the end to which he does it), but is not wicked, since his purpose is good; so that he is half-wicked. And he is not a criminal; for he does not act of malice aforethought; of the two types of incontinent man the one does not abide by the conclusions of his deliberation,
(20)
while the excitable man does not deliberate at all. And thus the incontinent man is like a city which passes all the right decrees and has good laws, but makes no use of them, as in Anaxandrides’ jesting remark,

               ‘The city willed it, that cares nought for laws’;

but the wicked man is like a city that uses its laws, but has wicked laws to use.

Now incontinence and continence are concerned with that which is in excess of the state characteristic of most men; for the continent man abides by his resolutions more and the incontinent man less than most men can.
(25)

Of the forms of incontinence, that of excitable people is more curable than that of those who deliberate but do not abide by their decisions, and those who are incontinent through habituation are more curable than those in whom incontinence is innate; for it is easier to change a habit than to change one’s nature; even habit is hard to change just because it is like nature,
(30)
as Evenus says:

               I say that habit’s but long practice, friend,

               And this becomes men’s nature in the end.

We have now stated what continence, incontinence, endurance,
(35)
and softness are, and how these states are related to each other.

11
     
[1152b]
The study of pleasure and pain belongs to the province of the political philosopher; for he is the architect of the end, with a view to which we call one thing bad and another good without qualification.
Further, it is one of our necessary tasks to consider them; for not only did we lay it down that moral virtue and vice are concerned with pains and pleasures,
36
(5)
but most people say that happiness involves pleasure; this is why the blessed man is called by a name derived from a word meaning enjoyment.
37

Now (1) some people think that no pleasure is a good, either in itself or incidentally, since the good and pleasure are not the same; (2) others think that some pleasures are good but that most are bad.
(10)
(3) Again there is a third view, that even if all pleasures are goods, yet the best thing in the world cannot be pleasure. (1) The reasons given for the view that pleasure is not a good at all are (
a
) that every pleasure is a perceptible process to a natural state, and that no process is of the same kind as its end, e. g. no process of building of the same kind as a house.
(15)
(
b
) A temperate man avoids pleasures. (
c
) A man of practical wisdom pursues what is free from pain, not what is pleasant. (
d
) The pleasures are a hindrance to thought, and the more so the more one delights in them, e. g. in sexual pleasure; for no one could think of anything while absorbed in this. (
e
) There is no art of pleasure; but every good is the product of some art. (
f
) Children and the brutes pursue pleasures. (2) The reasons for the view that not all pleasures are good are that (
a
) there are pleasures that are actually base and objects of reproach,
(20)
and (
b
) there are harmful pleasures; for some pleasant things are unhealthy. (3) The reason for the view that the best thing in the world is not pleasure is that pleasure is not an end but a process.

12
     These are pretty much the things that are said.
(25)
That it does not follow from these grounds that pleasure is not a good, or even the chief good, is plain from the following considerations. (A)
38
(
a
) First, since that which is good may be so in either of two senses (one thing good simply and another good for a particular person), natural constitutions and states of being, and therefore also the corresponding movements and processes, will be correspondingly divisible. Of those which are thought to be bad some will be bad if taken without qualification but not bad for a particular person, but worthy of his choice,
(30)
and some will not be worthy of choice even for a particular person, but only at a particular time and for a short period, though not without qualification; while others are not even pleasures, but seem to be so, viz. all those which involve pain and whose end is curative, e. g. the processes that go on in sick persons.

(
b
) Further, one kind of good being activity and another being state, the processes that restore us to our natural state are only incidentally pleasant; for that matter the activity at work in the appetites for them is the activity of so much of our state and nature as has remained unimpaired; for there are actually pleasures that involve
no
pain or appetite (e. g. those of contemplation),
(35)
the nature in such a case not being defective at all.
[1153a]
That the others are incidental is indicated by the fact that men do not enjoy the same pleasant objects when their nature is in its settled state as they do when it is being replenished, but in the former case they enjoy the things that are pleasant without qualification, in the latter the contraries of these as well; for then they enjoy even sharp and bitter things,
(5)
none of which is pleasant either by nature or without qualification. The states they produce, therefore, are not pleasures naturally or without qualification; for as pleasant things differ, so do the pleasures arising from them.

(
c
) Again, it is not necessary that there should be something else better than pleasure, as some say the end is better than the process; for pleasures are not processes nor do they all involve process—they are activities and ends; nor do they arise when we are becoming something,
(10)
but when we are exercising some faculty; and not all pleasures have an end different from themselves, but only the pleasures of persons who are being led to the perfecting of their nature. This is why it is not right to say that pleasure is perceptible process,
(15)
but it should rather be called activity of the natural state, and instead of ‘perceptible’ ‘unimpeded’. It is thought by
some
people to be process just because they think it is in the strict sense
good
; for they think that activity is process, which it is not.

(B)
39
The view that pleasures are bad because some pleasant things are unhealthy is like saying that healthy things are bad because some healthy things are bad for money-making; both are bad in the respect mentioned,
(20)
but they are not
bad
for
that
reason—indeed, thinking itself is sometimes injurious to health.

Neither practical wisdom nor any state of being is impeded by the pleasure arising from it; it is foreign pleasures that impede, for the pleasures arising from thinking and learning will make us think and learn all the more.

(C)
40
The fact that no pleasure is the product of any art arises naturally enough; there is no art of any other activity either,
(25)
but only of the corresponding faculty; though for that matter the arts of the perfumer and the cook
are
thought to be arts of pleasure.

(D)
41
The arguments based on the grounds that the temperate man avoids pleasure and that the man of practical wisdom pursues the painless life, and that children and the brutes pursue pleasure, are all refuted by the same consideration. We have pointed out
42
in what sense pleasures are good without qualification and in what sense some are not good; now both the brutes and children pursue pleasures of the latter kind (and the man of practical wisdom pursues tranquil freedom from that kind),
(30)
viz. those which imply appetite and pain, i. e. the bodily pleasures (for it is these that are of this nature) and the excesses of them, in respect of which the self-indulgent man is self-indulgent. This is why the temperate man avoids these pleasures; for even he
has
pleasures of his own.
(35)

BOOK: The Basic Works of Aristotle (Modern Library Classics)
4.56Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Looking for Alibrandi by Melina Marchetta
I Dream of Zombies by Johnstone, Vickie
The Arrogant Duke by Anne Mather
Death's Jest-Book by Reginald Hill
Her Client from Hell by Louisa George
Dizzy by Jolene Perry
The Tree of Story by Thomas Wharton
The Mad Voyage of Prince Malock by Timothy L. Cerepaka
Profiled by Andrews, Renee