The Blind Watchmaker (49 page)

Read The Blind Watchmaker Online

Authors: Richard Dawkins

Tags: #Science, #Life Sciences, #Evolution, #General

BOOK: The Blind Watchmaker
5.52Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

Even then, it isn’t logical. A physicist certainly doesn’t need Darwinism in order to do physics. He might think that biology is a trivial subject compared with physics. It would follow from this that, in his opinion, Darwinism is of trivial importance to science. But he could
not
sensibly conclude from this that it is therefore
false
Yet this is essentially what some of the leaders of the school of transformed cladistics seem to have done. ‘False’, note well, is precisely the word Nelson and Platnick used. Needless to say, their words have been picked up by the sensitive microphones that I mentioned in the previous chapter, and the result has been considerable publicity. They have earned themselves a place of honour in fundamentalist, creationist literature. When a leading transformed cladist came to give a guest lecture in my university recently, he drew a bigger crowd than any other guest lecturer that year! It isn’t hard to see why.

There is no doubt at all that remarks like ‘Darwinism … is a theory that has been put to the test and found false’, coming from established biologists on the staff of a respected national museum, will be meat and drink to creationists and others who actively have an interest in perpetrating falsehoods. This is the only reason I have troubled my readers with the topic of transformed cladism at all. As Mark Ridley more mildly said, in a review of the book in which Nelson and Platnick made that remark about Darwinism being false, Who would have guessed that all that they really
meant
was that ancestral species are tricky to represent in cladistic classification? Of course it is difficult to pin down the precise identity of ancestors, and there is a good case for not even trying to do so. But to make statements that encourage others to conclude that there never were any ancestors is to debauch language and betray truth.

Now I’d better go out and dig the garden, or something.

CHAPTER 11
DOOMED RIVALS

No serious biologist doubts the fact that evolution has happened, nor that all living creatures are cousins of one another. Some biologists, however, have had doubts about Darwin’s particular theory of
how
evolution happened. Sometimes this turns out to be just an argument about words. The theory of punctuated evolution, for instance, can be represented as anti-Darwinian. As I argued in Chapter 9, however, it is really a minor variety of Darwinism, and does not belong in any chapter about rival theories. But there are other theories that are most definitely
not
versions of Darwinism, theories that go flatly against the very spirit of Darwinism. These rival theories are the subject of this chapter. They include various versions of what is called Lamarckism; also other points of view such as ‘neutralism’, ‘mutationism’ and creationism which have, from time to time, been advanced as alternatives to Darwinian selection.

The obvious way to decide between rival theories is to examine the evidence. Lamarckian types of theory, for instance, are traditionally rejected - and rightly so - because no good evidence for them has ever been found (not for want of energetic trying, in some cases by zealots prepared to fake evidence). In this chapter I shall take a different tack, largely because so many other books have examined the evidence and concluded in favour of Darwinism. Instead of examining the evidence for and against rival theories, I shall adopt a more armchair approach. My argument will be that Darwinism is the only known theory that is in principle
capable
of explaining certain aspects of life. If I am right it means that, even if there were no actual evidence in favour of the Darwinian theory (there is, of course) we should still be justified in preferring it over all rival theories.

One way in which to dramatize this point is to make a prediction. I predict that, if a form of life is ever discovered in another part of the universe, however outlandish and weirdly alien that form of life may be in detail, it will be found to resemble life on Earth in one key respect: it will have evolved by some kind of Darwinian natural selection. Unfortunately, this is a prediction that we shall, in all probability, not be able to test in our lifetimes, but it remains a way of dramatizing an important truth about life on our own planet. The Darwinian theory is in principle capable of explaining life. No other theory that has ever been suggested is in principle capable of explaining life. I shall demonstrate this by discussing all known rival theories, not the evidence for or against them, but their adequacy, in principle, as explanations for life.

First, I must specify what it means to ‘explain’ life. There are, of course, many properties of living things that we could list, and some of them might be explicable by rival theories. Many facts about the distribution of protein molecules, as we have seen, may be due to neutral genetic mutations rather than Darwinian selection. There is one particular property of living things, however, that I want to single out as explicable
only
by Darwinian selection. This property is the one that has been the recurring topic of this book: adaptive complexity. Living organisms are well fitted to survive and reproduce in their environments, in ways too numerous and statistically improbable to have come about in a single chance blow. Following Paley, I have used the example of the eye. Two or three of an eye’s well-‘designed’ features could, conceivably, have come about in a single lucky accident. It is the sheer number of interlocking parts, all well adapted to seeing and well adapted to each other, that demands a special kind of explanation beyond mere chance. The Darwinian explanation, of course, involves chance too, in the form of mutation. But the chance is filtered cumulatively by selection, step by step, over many generations. Other chapters have shown that this theory is capable of providing a satisfying explanation for adaptive complexity. In this chapter I shall argue that all other known theories are not capable of so doing.

First, let us take Darwinism’s most prominent historical rival, Lamarckism. When Lamarckism was first proposed in the early nineteenth century, it was not as a rival to Darwinism, because Darwinism had not yet been thought of. The Chevalier de Lamarck was ahead of his time. He was one of those eighteenth-century intellectuals who argued in favour of evolution. In this he was right, and he would deserve to be honoured for this alone, along with Charles Darwin’s grandfather Erasmus and others. Lamarck also offered the best theory of the mechanism of evolution that anyone could come up with at the time, but there is no reason to suppose that, if the Darwinian theory of mechanism had been around at the time, he would have rejected it. It was not around, and it is Lamarck’s misfortune that, at least in the English-speaking world, his name has become a label for an error - his theory of the
mechanism
of evolution rather than for his correct belief in the
fact
that evolution has occurred. This is not a history book, and I shall not attempt a scholarly dissection of exactly what Lamarck himself said. There was a dose of mysticism in Lamarck’s actual words - for instance, he had a strong belief in progress up what many people, even today, think of as the ladder of life; and he spoke of animals striving as if they, in some sense, consciously
wanted to
evolve. I shall extract from Lamarckism those non-mystical elements which, at least at first sight, seem to have a sporting chance of offering a real alternative to Darwinism. These elements, the only ones adopted by modern ‘neo-Lamarckians’, are basically two: the inheritance of acquired characteristics, and the principle of use and disuse.

The principle of use and disuse states that those parts of an organism’s body that are used grow larger. Those parts that are not used tend to wither away. It is an observed fact that when you exercise particular muscles they grow; muscles that are never used shrink. By examining a man’s body we can tell which muscles he uses and which he does not. We may even be able to guess his profession or his recreation. Enthusiasts of the ‘body-building’ cult make use of the principle of use and disuse to ‘build’ their bodies, almost like a piece of sculpture, into whatever unnatural shape is demanded by fashion in this peculiar minority culture. Muscles are not the only parts of the body that respond to use in this kind of way. Walk barefoot, and you acquire tougher skin on your soles. It is easy to tell a farmer from a bank clerk by looking at their hands alone. The farmer’s hands are horny, toughened by long exposure to rough work. If the clerk’s hands are horny at all, it amounts only to a little callus on the writing finger.

The principle of use and disuse enables animals to become better at the job of surviving in their world, progressively better during their own lifetime as a result of living in that world. Humans, through direct exposure to sunlight, or lack of it, develop a skin colour which equips them better to survive in the particular local conditions. Too much sunlight is dangerous. Enthusiastic sunbathers with very fair skins are susceptible to skin cancer. Too little sunlight, on the other hand, leads to vitamin-D deficiency and rickets, sometimes seen in hereditarily black children living in Scandinavia. The brown pigment melanin, which is synthesized under the influence of sunlight, makes a screen to protect the underlying tissues from the harmful effects of further sunlight. If a suntanned person moves to a less sunny climate the melanin disappears, and the body is able to benefit from what little sun there is. This can be represented as an instance of the principle of use and disuse: skin goes brown when it is ‘used’, and fades to white when it is not ‘used’. Some tropical races, of course, inherit a thick screen of melanin whether or not they are exposed to sunlight as individuals.

Now turn to the other main Lamarckian principle, the idea that such acquired characteristics are then inherited by future generations. All evidence suggests that this idea is simply false, but through most of history it has been believed to be true. Lamarck did not invent it, but simply incorporated the folk wisdom of his time. In some circles it is still believed. My mother had a dog who occasionally affected a limp, holding up one hind leg and hobbling on the other three. A neighbour had an older dog who had unfortunately lost one hind leg in a car accident. She was convinced that her dog must be the father of my mother’s dog, the evidence being that he had obviously inherited his limp. Folk wisdom and fairy tales are filled with similar legends. Many people either believe, or would like to believe, in the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Until this century it was the dominant theory of heredity among serious biologists too. Darwin himself believed in it, but it was not a part of his theory of evolution so his name is not linked to it in our minds.

If you put the inheritance of acquired characteristics together with the principle of use and disuse, you have what looks like a good recipe for evolutionary improvement. It is this recipe that is commonly labelled the Lamarckian theory of evolution. If successive generations toughen their feet by walking barefoot over rough ground, each generation, so the theory goes, will have a slightly tougher skin than the generation before. Each generation gets an advantage over its predecessor. In the end, babies will be born with already toughened feet (which as a matter of fact they are, though for a different reason as we shall see). If successive generations bask in the tropical sun, they will go browner and browner as, according to the Lamarckian theory, each generation will inherit some of the previous generation’s tan. In time they will be born black (again as a matter of fact they are, but not for the Lamarckian reason).

The legendary examples are the blacksmith’s arms and the giraffe’s neck. In villages where the blacksmith inherited his trade from his father, grandfather and great grandfather before him, he was thought to inherit the well-trained muscles of his ancestors too. Not just inherit them but add to them through his own exercise, and pass on the improvements to his son. Ancestral giraffes with short necks desperately needed to reach high leaves on trees. They strove mightily upwards, thereby stretching neck muscles and bones. Each generation ended up with a slightly longer neck than its predecessor, and it passed its head start on to the next generation. All evolutionary advancement, according to the pure Lamarckian theory, follows this pattern. The animal strives for something that it needs. As a result the parts of the body used in the striving grow larger, or otherwise change in an appropriate direction. The change is inherited by the next generation and so the process goes on. This theory has the advantage that it is cumulative - an essential ingredient of any theory of evolution if it is to fulfil its role in our world view, as we have seen.

The Lamarckian theory seems to have great emotional appeal, for certain types of intellectual as well as for laymen. I was once approached by a colleague, a celebrated Marxist historian and a most cultivated and well-read man. He understood, he said, that the facts all seemed to be against the Lamarckian theory, but was there really no hope that it might be true? I told him that in my opinion there was none, and he accepted this with sincere regret, saying that for ideological reasons he had wanted Lamarckism to be true. It seemed to offer such positive hopes for the betterment of humanity. George Bernard Shaw devoted one of his enormous Prefaces (in
Back to Methuselah) to
a passionate advocacy of the inheritance of acquired characteristics. His case was based not upon biological knowledge, of which he would cheerfully have admitted he had none. It was based upon an emotional loathing of the implications of Darwinism, that ‘chapter of accidents’:

it seems simple, because you do not at first realize all that it involves. But when its whole significance dawns on you, your heart sinks into a heap of sand within you. There is a hideous fatalism about it, a ghastly and damnable reduction of beauty and intelligence, of strength and purpose, of honor and aspiration.

Arthur Koestler was another distinguished man of letters who could not abide what he saw as the implications of Darwinism. As Stephen Gould has sardonically but correctly put it, throughout his last six books Koestler conducted ‘a campaign against his own misunderstanding of Darwinism’. He sought refuge in an alternative which was never entirely clear to me but which can be interpreted as an obscure version of Lamarckism.

Other books

Storm Child by Sharon Sant
Edge of Flight by Kate Jaimet
Stormrider by P. A. Bechko
Rise of the Blood by Lucienne Diver
Forever Odd by Dean Koontz
Murder Under the Tree by Bernhardt, Susan
God of Clocks by Alan Campbell