It Began with Babbage (35 page)

Read It Began with Babbage Online

Authors: Subrata Dasgupta

BOOK: It Began with Babbage
4.87Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

Figure 11.2
shows a neuron with two excitatory synapses
A
and
B
, and one inhibitory synapse
C
as inputs. The threshold value is 1. If the inhibitory synapse is inactive, then activation of
A
or
B
will excite the neuron and it will “fire.” However, if the inhibitory synapse
c
is active, then no matter what the states of excitation of
A
and
B
, the neuron will not excite. The Boolean proposition describing this neuron is
D
= (
A
OR
B
) AND (NOT
C
).

McCulloch and Pitts described the behavior of both single neurons and neuron networks in terms of Boolean propositions or expressions. The correspondence with switching circuit behavior as Shannon described in 1938 (see
Chapter 5
, Section IV) is evident to anyone familiar with Shannon's work. Although the notation used by McCulloch and Pitts and the mathematics they present to demonstrate their “logical calculus” were complex, their core result was clear. The behavior of neural activity could be described by Boolean (logical) expressions; conversely, any Boolean proposition could be realized by a network of McCulloch-Pitts neurons, and although the neurons themselves are simple in behavior, they can give rise to neuron systems of considerable complexity.

FIGURE
11.1 An Abstract Neuron with Excitatory Inputs.

FIGURE
11.2 An Abstract Neuron with an Inhibitory Input.

IV

Let us leave aside how their article was received by its primary target readers—the neurophysiological and theoretical biological community. Its place in this story lies in that it caught the attention of the irrepressible von Neumann. Tucked away in the EDVAC report, written two years after the publication of the McCulloch-Pitts article, was an observation of the “all-or-none” character of relay elements in digital computing devices.
14
But then, von Neumann continued, the neurons in the brains of “higher animals” also manifest this binary character; they possess two states: “quiescent” and “excited.”
15
Referring to the McCulloch-Pitts article, von Neumann noted that the behavior of neurons could be “imitated” by such binary artifacts as telegraph relays and vacuum tubes.
16

The parallel between binary circuit elements (relays and vacuum tubes) in a digital computer and neurons in the brain is thus established. Drawing on the McCulloch-Pitts neuron, von Neumann envisioned digital circuits as a network of idealized circuit elements, which he called
E-elements
, that “receives the excitatory and inhibitory stimuli and emits its own stimuli”
17
after an appropriate fixed “synaptic delay.”
18
A significant portion of the EDVAC report is then devoted to the description of the E-elements and networks of E-elements, including the structure and behavior of arithmetic circuits modeled by such networks.
19

von Neumann had, albeit briefly, almost casually identified a relationship between the circuits in the brain and circuits in the digital computer, but this was merely a scenting of blood. For a man of his restless intellectual capacity and curiosity, these allusions in the EDVAC report were only the beginning of a new scientific track.

In September 1948, a number of scientists from different disciplines—mathematics, neurophysiology, and psychology—assembled in Pasadena, California. They were participating in a conference titled Cerebral Mechanisms in Behavior, funded by the Hixon Foundation and, thus, named the Hixon Symposium.
20
This symposium has an important
place in the histories of psychology and cognitive science. Behaviorism, the dogma that eschewed any discussion of mind, mentalism, cognition as being within the purview of scientific psychology—a dogma that became the dominant paradigm in American experimental psychology throughout much of the first half of the 20th century from the time of World War I—came under serious attack from people such as McCulloch and neuropsychologist Karl Lashley (1890–1958).

And there was von Neumann. In a lecture later published in the Hixon Symposium proceedings as a 40-page chapter, he pursued in some detail the blood he had scented 3 years before. He titled his exposition “The General and Logical Theory of Automata.”
21

If Leonardo Torres y Quevedo had redirected the old idea of automata from active to
thinking
artifacts in 1915 (see
Chapter 3
, Section IX), if Alan Turing had launched a branch of intellectual inquiry into how abstract automata could work with his
Entscheidungsproblem
paper of 1936 (see
Chapter 4
, Section III), then by way of his Hixon paper, Neumann surely gave the field a name. The subject of
automata theory
is not the automata of Hellenistic antiquity, but abstract computational machines such as the Turing machine. The epicenter of what would later be called
theoretical computer science
lay at the door of automata theory.

V

The kind of theory von Neumann advocated for the study of automata lay in the realm of mathematics and logic. In this he followed the approach adopted by McCulloch and Pitts. It was to be an
axiomatic
theory. Beginning with fundamental undefined concepts, assumptions, and propositions (axioms), and using well-understood rules of reasoning, one derives logical consequences of these fundamentals (see
Chapter 4
, Section I for a brief discussion of the axiomatic approach). The axiomatic world, familiar to those of a mathematical or logical disposition,
22
is a formal world, quite unlike the severely empirical world that people like Wilkes, Kilburn, and Mauchly inhabited. Abstract automata, like actual digital electronic computers, are artifacts—inventions of the human mind—but electronic computers belong to the realm of the empirical; abstract automata belong to the realm of the formal. And so, axiomatizing the behavior of abstract automata meant that their building blocks be treated as “black boxes” with internal structures that are ignored (or abstracted away), but with functional behaviors that are well defined and visible.
23
Defining the behavior of McCulloch-Pitts neurons by logical (Boolean) expressions was an instance of the axiomatization of actual neurons. Their internal structure, which obeys the laws of physics and chemistry, can be ignored.
24

This approach is bread and butter to mathematicians and logicians, and, indeed, to certain theoretical physicists and biologists. But, von Neumann cautioned, there is a fundamental limitation of the axiomatic approach when applied to empirical objects such as neurons. The approach is only as good as the fundamental assumptions or axioms. One
must be sure that the axioms are
valid
and are
consistent
with observed reality. The formal world must have resonance with the empirical world. To ensure this validity, the theorist has to rely on the empirical scientists—in the case of neurons, the neurophysiologists and biochemists.
25

von Neumann's primary concern was not neurons in the head but “artificial automata”—more specifically, computing machines.
26
And although such automata are vastly less complicated than the nervous system, he found the idea of investigating the behavior of neural machines in terms of automata enticing—hence the comparative study of neural systems in living matter and artificial automata. More ambitiously, it could be claimed that he was aiming to establish a
universal
automata theory that applied as much to the natural as to the artificial, unifying nature and artifact in some specific sense. von Neumann was, of course, quite aware that the neuron has both binary, digital (“all-or-none”),
and
nondigital or analog characteristics.
27
In contrast, computing machines of the kind recently conceived were digital.
28
Nonetheless, as a stage of the axiomatic approach one could consider the living organism
as if
it was a purely digital automaton.
29
This suggested, to von Neumann, that there were two kinds of automata—natural and artificial, a first step in unification and universalization. Moreover, even though such artifacts as the electromechanical relay and the electronic vacuum tube were digital entities, they were really rather complicated analog mechanisms that obeyed the laws of physics. They
become
digital entities under certain restricted conditions.
30
There was, then, a small difference between such devices and biological neurons.
31
Neither was really of an all-or-nothing character, but both could be so regarded if (a) they could operate under certain conditions in an all-or-nothing manner and (b) such operating conditions were the normal conditions under which they would be used.
32

Like relays and vacuum tubes, biological neurons are electrical switching units.
33
This, of course, was the assumption undergirding the McCulloch-Pitts model of nervous activity, which enabled them to draw on Boolean logic to describe the behavior of neuron networks.

However, McCulloch and Pitts were not interested in computers per se, whereas von Neumann was. And so, comparison between organisms and computing machines—between the natural and the artificial—followed: their relative sizes in terms of the number of basic switching elements (the central nervous system, according to estimates of the time, had 10
10
neurons
34
; existing machines such as the ENIAC or the IBM version of the Harvard Mark I had about 20,000 switching elements—relays and vacuum tubes
35
), the relative sizes of the switching organs (“the vacuum tube … is gigantic compared to a nerve cell,” the ratio of the sizes “about a billion” to one
36
), and the relative switching speeds (that is, the speed at which digital elements can switch states from active to inactive or vice versa); vacuum tubes were vastly faster than neurons, with the switching speed ratio being something like 1200:1.
37

von Neumann did not actually present an axiomatic theory of automata but, rather, the promise of such a theory. There were already, he noted, prior results that would contribute
to this theory: the McCulloch-Pitts theory according to which the functions of nervous activity can be described by a formal (or abstract or idealized) Pitts-McCulloch neural network,
38
and Turing's description and construction of an abstract computing machine (in particular, his formulation of a universal automaton that could perform computations performed by any other computing machine).
39

But von Neumann went beyond what Turing or McCulloch and Pitts had offered. He reasoned that if automata theory was to be universal in scope, embracing the natural and the artificial, it had to tackle the problem of
self-reproduction
, for in this lay the essence of biological systems. And for this, Turing's universal computing machine did not suffice. Turing's machine could only produce as output, strings of 0s and 1s on a tape. von Neumann's vision was more daring; he desired automata that could produce as output
other automata
.
40

So the “General” in the title of his article went beyond unifying natural and artificial computers. Although the universal Turing machine allowed for computational universality, what von Neumann sought was also
constructive
universality.
41
It was no longer a matter of comparing cerebration with computation, but of uniting the organic and the mechanical in a more fundamental sense—the possibility, so to speak, of “artificial life.”

von Neumann then speculated in a general way on the construction of such a self-reproducing automaton. Consider first an automaton A that has associated with it a description of itself,
d
(A). Using this description, A produces a copy of itself. However, A is not self-reproducing because it does not make a copy of its own description,
d
(A). So next consider another automaton, B, that when supplied with
d
(A), makes a copy of just this description.

Other books

Laura Possessed by Anthea Fraser
Holier Than Thou by Buzo, Laura
Lost Empire by Cussler, Clive;Grant Blackwood
Broken Beauty by Chloe Adams
In the Blood by Jackie French
Aces by Alanson, Craig
Brother Sun, Sister Moon by Katherine Paterson
Wild Hyacinthe (Crimson Romance) by Sarina, Nola, Faith, Emily
Guilty Thing Surprised by Ruth Rendell
Princes of Charming by Fox, Georgia